Modality, propositional functions, and logical learning: a historical look at the conflict between Kripke and Frege-Russell in the preface to Naming and Necessity
DOI:
https://doi.org/10.25247/P1982-999X.2023.v23n3.p170-190Keywords:
Modality, Rigidity, Logical fallibilism, Analysis, Propositional functionsAbstract
We argue that the technical advantages of rigidity are not the most important factor in accepting Kripke's thesis against Frege-Russell (sense-wide-scope). Kripke's philosophical thesis is far removed from Frege-Russell's in that the former evaluates the function of "identity" in a different - metaphysical - way than the latter. In this paper, we argue that the discussion can evolve along a different path: evaluating and assessing the divergence between different conceptions of counterfactual knowledge, and studying the motives and prices that seemed reasonable to Russell-Frege to deal with the modal problem without expanding the extensional universe of classical logic. In particular, we will consider the merits of the Russellian option, understood as a theory of logical knowledge of the various ways in which a proposition can be false, depending on how we analyze the anti-extension of the proposition using propositional functions. Modal predicates can essentially be understood within the structures of fallible truth models by finding an extensional interpretation for counterfactual scenarios and extensionalizing complex identities. This provides a non-metaphysical understanding of what happens when one learns something logically about modality and counterfactuality.
Downloads
References
DEJNOSKA, Dan. Bertrand Russell on Modality and Logical Relevance. 2. ed. Publisher: Jan Dejnozka ISBN: 13: 978–1478292616, 10: 147829261X, 2015.
DUMMETT, Michael. The Interpretation of Frege’s Philosophy. Harvard University Press. 1981.
EVANS, Gareth. The Varieties of Reference. Oxford: Oxford U. P. 1982.
FREGE, Gotlob. Sense and Reference. Reviewed work(s): Source: The Philosophical Review, v. 57, n. 3, may/1948, p. 209-230. Published by: Duke University Press on behalf of Philosophical Review Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2181485. 1948.
JAMES, Connelly. Russell's Contribution to Philosophy of Language. Review of Graham Stevens, The Theory of Descriptions: Russell and the Philosophy of Language. Russell: The Journal of Bertrand Russell Studies, 33 (1). 2013.
MARCUS, Ruth Barcan. Modalities and intensional languages. Synthese 13 (4):303-322. 1961.
QUINE, W. V. O. Logic and the reification of universals. 2. ed. In: From a Logical Point of View. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, p. 102–129. (First edition 1953). 1980.
QUINE, W.V.O, 1994. The Ways of Paradox. (Harvard University Press, 1966,1976; 1994
KRIPKE, Saul. Naming and Necessity. Harvard Press. 2001
STEVENS, Graham. The Theory of Descriptions: Russell and the Philosophy of Language. Palgrave-Macmillan. 2011.
RUSSELL, Bertrand. On Denoting. Mind, New Series, v. 14, No. 56. (Oct., 1905), p. 479-493. 1905.
RUSSELL, Bertrand. The Philosophy of Logical Atomism. London and New York, Routledge Classics, 2010.
RUSSELL, Bertrand. Mysticism, Logic and Other Essays. London, George Allen & Unwin Ltd. 1917.
SOAMES, Scott. No class: Russell on contextual definition and the elimination of sets. Philosophical Studies, v. 139, p. 213-218, 2008.
Downloads
Published
Issue
Section
License
Copyright (c) 2023 Lucas Ribeiro Vollet
This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License.
You are free to:
- Share — copy and redistribute the material in any medium or format for any purpose, even commercially.
- Adapt — remix, transform, and build upon the material for any purpose, even commercially.
- The licensor cannot revoke these freedoms as long as you follow the license terms.
Under the following terms:
- Attribution — You must give appropriate credit , provide a link to the license, and indicate if changes were made . You may do so in any reasonable manner, but not in any way that suggests the licensor endorses you or your use.
- No additional restrictions — You may not apply legal terms or technological measures that legally restrict others from doing anything the license permits.
Notices:
You do not have to comply with the license for elements of the material in the public domain or where your use is permitted by an applicable exception or limitation .
No warranties are given. The license may not give you all of the permissions necessary for your intended use. For example, other rights such as publicity, privacy, or moral rights may limit how you use the material.